Today, two stories. The first is impersonal, and is about the difficulty of handling immediacy and specificity in the context of State violence. The second is personal, and is about the difficulty of handling abstraction and generality in the context of personal agency. Two angles on the same cultural phenomenon.
One: No Theatre for Achilles
Writes Graeber,
We are not used to thinking of nursing homes or banks or even HMOs as violent institutionsâexcept perhaps in the most abstract and metaphorical sense. But the violence Iâm referring to here is not abstract. I am not speaking of conceptual violence. I am speaking of violence in the literal sense: the kind that involves, say, one person hitting another over the head with a wooden stick. All of these are institutions involved in the allocation of resources within a system of property rights regulated and guaranteed by governments in a system that ultimately rests on the threat of force. âForceâ in turn is just a euphemistic way to refer to violence: that is, the ability to call up people dressed in uniforms, willing to threaten to hit others over the head with wooden sticks.
It is curious how rarely citizens in industrial democracies actually think about this fact, or how instinctively we try to discount its importance. This is what makes it possible, for example, for graduate students to be able to spend days in the stacks of university libraries poring over Foucault-inspired theoretical tracts about the declining importance of coercion as a factor in modern life without ever reflecting on that fact that, had they insisted on their right to enter the stacks without showing a properly stamped and validated ID, armed men would have been summoned to physically remove them, using whatever force might be required. Itâs almost as if the more we allow aspects of our everyday existence to fall under the purview of bureaucratic regulations, the more everyone concerned colludes to downplay the fact (perfectly obvious to those actually running the system) that all of it ultimately depends on the threat of physical harm. (58)
A subterranean question that Iâm interested in surfacing: by what meansâpsychological, cultural, political, economicâare the âarmed menâ in this story rendered willing and able to cause physical harm to total strangers in libraries? Or, in another context: what is the process by which The State convinces its pilots to fly reaper drones?
A simple, too-cute answer: itâs the uniforms.
Well, itâs not the uniforms per se. Instead, more precisely, itâs a network of relations that makes uniforms seem possible as natural kinds. Itâs a web of symbols and significationâa worldview, an ontologyâthat reorients those who exist within it around extremely stylised notions of identity and ethical behaviour.
You write that
To motivate yourself into certain actsâto be an actor (in the sense of someone who does things)âsometimes relies on the transformation of self into an actor (someone who pretends to be a certain kind of character who would do those acts).
I disagree. To be an agent is to be someone who does things in the environment in response to desires and expectations; to be an actor is to be someone who does things in the course of fulfilling a role. The distinction is subtle, but important. In many harsh (or âimmediateâ, or âconcreteâ) environments, the âmotivationâ to act is immanent in oneâs relation to the environment. Think of the way you are when youâre hiking. Or the way a dingo acts. Or an albatross. Think, also, of how you feel about the suffering of farmed animals. I donât mean how you feel about it âas an abstractionâ, or as that kind of something which most people flinch away from receiving any information about. How do you feel about the suffering of factory farmed animals when you consider that suffering as the visible consequence of real events in the real world?
The thing Iâm claiming is that a certain kind of theatricality is a sufficient (though not necessary) pre-condition for motivating some kinds of anonymous, Us-vs-Them, Group-on-Group violence. Individual violence is plainly possible. Even âsmall groupâ violence arising from the control of territorially-bound resources seems ânaturalâ enough. But the kinds of things that modern soldiers (predominantly) do are importantly unlike the kinds of things Achilles does. And the murders perpetrated by modern soldiers are (even in fiction) characterised in ways that are, as you rightly point out, importantly unlike the death of Alcathous.
The threatricality isnât something that happens âin parallelâ with this âGroup As Moral Patientâ phenomenon. Rather, theatricality is a means of traumatisation, of moral injury, of destroying and reconstructing the âindividualâ so that they are more reliably âactor, not agentâ.
While Iâm not the first to say this, itâs relevant here: to a first approximation, The Iliad is a story of a powerful aristocratic figure (Agamemnon) trying to translate more personal forms of warfare (which focused on âraiding for glory and stolen resourcesâ) into a modern, transpersonal, impersonal form. And itâs a story of that project basically failing. Agamemnon tries to turn early agrarian warfare (identifiable individuals fighting over territory) into the kind of thing that the American army as an institution does today. But, well, it doesnât work.
In some of the post-Homeric stories, Achillesâhidden on Skyrosâmakes one of the only truly free choices in Greek mythology. If Achilles stays away, he knows that the Greeks will lose the war, but he also knows that heâll die as a happy old farmer. That heâll be loved by his sons, remembered by his grandchildren, and then (in a few generationsâ time) forgotten. If he instead takes up the spear, heâll die in the war. Young and bloody. But with his help, the Greeks will sack Troy, and his nameâAchillesâ nameâwill last for millennia, synonymous with âheroâ and âwarriorâ. Only by dying at Troy can Achilles burn away the last mortal parts of himself. Only there can he finish what Thetis started.
Achilles, of course, goes to war. Heâs a young man, trained by Chiron, and heâs the human embodiment of the phrase âtoo much testosteroneâ. Picking glory over longevity is what young men do. And itâs the thing that old men make use of. And because Agamemnon fails in his project, Achilles isâfrom the perspective of maximising the interests of The Groupâallowed to remain too much of an individual agent, and not enough of an actor. Achilles is a great warrior, but a terrible soldier. Theatricality, moral injury, trauma ⌠these are the means by which modern soldiers are produced. And the means by which anonymous armed men can be motivated to âuse forceâ against strangers in libraries (or sleeping in doorways), as manifestations of institutions that are necessarily patriarchal and racist at their root.
Modern states such as America and Australia rely heavily on small teams of highly-trained, âspecialâ forces to enact the most personal violence. And itâs a fraught affair. First, as far as I can tell, modern States find themselves in need of extremely specialised, personalised, high-precision forms of personal violence. The occasional Achilles, in addition to a cop. First, the State tries to (re)construct low-fidelity simulacra of Men Like Achilles from a subset the already-usefully-traumatised-and-reliable mass of ordinary soldiers. This doesnât work, or rarely does, and so the system instead resigns itself to selecting people who canât or wonât submit to ordinary military structures andâat a kind of strange âarmâs lengthâ removeâallows the older and more experienced of these to recruit, train, instruct, and direct the younger and less experienced ones. Provided these small teams are sufficiently violent in useful-to-the-State ways, theyâre given the resources and freedom to develop a kind of parallel culture. It barely interfaces with the normal military, because it barely can. Inside a given team, one sees largely structureless, formal-hierarchy-disrespecting, positive-sum interactions; members of these communities believe, fundamentally, that every person and thing âoutsideâ their is mere environment or terrain (and so not morally relevant). Including their ostensible commanders.
The State tries to narrativise these groups of Extremely Personal Violence Executors in ways that are more palatable or comprehensible to ordinary citizens (eg. heavily-funded fiction such as the âSeal Teamâ). The system finds excuses for their beards and lack of uniform. The system does its best to titrate Achilles-like glory. The system does its best to tame the monsters it needs. It mostly fails. The reality breaks through. These people look like us, and talk like us, but theyâre from a culture thatâs alien even to the larger military that produced it.
(Compare the fiction to the reality.)
The theatricality to which I am referring is not a precursor or precondition of Achilles. Itâs a thing that someone like Agamemnon is using (or, at least, the cultural system which generates Agamemnon is using) in an attempt to create the useful-to-the-State attitude of the blank-faced bureaucracy, or the Nazi Guard.
Two: As Christian Patriarch
I was talking to my mother about her fatherâletâs call him Dâa while ago. Dâs got Late Stage Parkinsonâs Disease, and heâs been in a nursing home for a few years now. Itâs a good nursing home, as they go, and a necessary situation. My grandmother couldnât care for him at home and, really, nobody could. But heâs miserable. He wants to die, but canât. Heâs felt this way for years. Itâs not a great scene.
The other day, I wrote:
While at first nobody believes the masks theyâre holding up are ârealâ, the moral injury inflicted by the things theyâve been complicit in has made removing masks impossible. All they can do is switch from role to role. What seemed at first to be a temporary âplayâ becomes embodied as The Real for its players. One is motivated, now, to redefine identity and being for oneself. One redefines belief. One naturalises masks. And, as a matter of psychological survival, one is motivated to continue that re-definition until everything is theatre. Itâs a one-way street.
I found myself trying to explain this to my mother, in the way that adult children sometimes do in tense relationships with parents. I failed. Maybe itâs generational. I donât know. Iâll try again here.
My mother is confused, I think, in her distress. Or maybe sheâs flinching away from what she doesnât want to see.
By her account, for yearsâsince before D went into full-time careâmy mother would have these interactions with her dad. The three of them would sit togetherâmy mother, my grandmother, and Dâand heâd be chipper and cheerful. Then, my grandmother would leave the room to make tea, answer the phone, whatever. And D would suddenly switch.
âI canât keep this up,â heâd say, in a moment of grim honestly, âAnd neither can she. Iâm not going to get better. Youâve got to help me.â
Then my grandmother would return, and heâd be chipper again.
If my mother tried to bring up Dâs stated âprivatelyâ-stated feelings in larger conversations with him and others (my grandmother, a doctor, whoever), heâd play it off and minimise it, or deny it outright. His suffering was realâis realâbut it was like heâd reached a negotiated settlement within himself, where heâd admit it to his daughter but not his wife.
He still does this. In the nursing home, to just my mother, heâll say openly that he wants to die. But when she sits with him and his GP, as she doesâas he asks her to doâhe canât seem to bring himself to make a plan.
The closest he came to it was when he first moved into the nursing home; to his doctor, Iâm told, he said he wanted to go off most of his medications, so that a chronic infection in his hip would take hold and speed things along. But he couldnât seem to articulate it forcefully enough, to anyone, and so the doctorâs line was âitâs a distressing time, a lot of change; letâs put you on an antidepressent and revisit the issue once youâre settled.â (True and reasonable.)
Now itâs three years later and everything is worse.
Hereâs the thing about my grandfather. He was a methodist missionary, in Africa, before the family was deported from the country because of his support of a union movement and the end of white colonial rule. Later, he was a leader in the church. Deeply sympathetic to what I think he and I would both call âQuaker valuesâ. Then, as my grandmother puts it, âfeminism happenedâ. They left the church and, with some others, formed an âintentional communityâ that remains stable to this day. He was a teacher, and a community leader, in a deeply Christian mold.
My mother seems confused because she thinks that, when he articulates his preferences to her, that means he wants to act on them. When he canât articulate those same preferences to his wife or doctor, she thinks he just needs help or encouragement to do so.
The sad fact is: I think heâs switching between artificial roles that are so deeply ingrained heâs naturalised them as âselfâ.
I asked my mother to look back on her own memories of childhood.
âHow many separate memories do you have of him,â I asked, âwhere he came home lateâvisibly exhausted, angry, or depressedâbecause he was putting first the preferences of some other group of people you hardly knew?â
âThose are the only memories I have of him,â she said.
This is the ugly heart of so-called Christian Values, and the role of the Christian Patriarch that a man like him had internalised as âmoral actionâ.
On a deep level, he thinks that itâs his duty to sacrifice himself: to subjugate his needs, and suffer in order to lessen (or somehow âbearâ) the suffering of others. At home, as the patriarch, heâs the Provider of his house. And in the worldâin every community he was part ofâhis Polaris was something like âIs this self-sacrifice? If so, it must be good for the group. It must be moral.â
No amount of âprogressive valuesâ, or âfeminism happened in the churchâ, or âleaving the churchâ, or âintentional communityâ, actually replaced this decision framework. Itâs too ingrained. And itâs too widespread. Itâs not just Christian, now, itâs Western and itâs modern.
There is uncertainty about whether âgoodâ means âgood for the individualâ or âgood for the groupâ or âbothâ. In Christianity, with Original Sin, the only good is âgood for the groupâ. And so the individual Christian is taught to utilise an imperfect proxy measure for âgoodâ: bad for me. And then Goodheartâs Law does its work. For two thousand years.
The earlier account I gave was framed in terms of an entangled violence/theatre/spectacle object in the cultural superstructure. While I think I probably owe more precise definitions of âviolenceâ, âtheatreâ, and âspectacleâ, in the meantime Iâll try to clarify the edges of that account.
To my knowledge, my grandfather was never engaged in any spectacle violence. However, the explanation of his behavior that best fits the facts is that heâs doing the exact same thingâpsychologicallyâthat you say participants in spectacle violence necessarily do: heâs generating his behavior from an understanding of generic âpartsâ he knows how to play.
Heâs not a coherent agent who looks for things that are at least good for him and mostly good for both him and others. Heâs assuming a zero-sum dynamic, everywhere, and then behaving as if âlosing in the zero-sum dynamicâ is what A Moral Person does.
For years, heâs had a coherent preference to die. He wonât act on it. He canât act on it. He will, however, articulate it to his daughter. Why?
I think itâs because the role he plays with his daughterâthe drama they play outâis one of âailing fatherâ and âdoting daughterâ. She gets to feel like sheâs a caring âgood daughterâ and he gets to feel pride at having raised (having socialised) a daughter who plays this legible part so well. When both were younger, he was the disciplinarian, the distant father, and she was the rebellious teen. Now the arc of the narrative finds purchase: he softens, opens up to her, and she fulfills the role as feminine carer.
When heâs with his wife, however, heâs playing the part of âChristian husbandâ. He sacrifices for her and hides, as best he can, the very fact and extent of his sacrifice. He falsifies his preferences to himself so that hersâor rather, his model of hersâcan be better satisfied. For this, he is emotionally rewarded. Externally, Iâm sure, there are social rewards: heâs brave in the face of a degenerative illness, as is expected of A Man Like Him. There are also internal rewards. A âsocietyâ within him, acting as the generating function.
And he does this so naturally, so instinctively, that he doesnât even see it.