Today: a zeroth draft; a few parts; the beginning of a series.
§ 1. We Set Fire To Things
âHow many decisions of meaning do we actually make,â you ask, âin our lives?â
Itâs true; weâre watery bundles. Sinew, nerve, reflex, habit. Even when we play at being cautious and careful, as you say,
Itâs just weâre a mess. We set fire to things simply out of curiosity. Every generation in living memory has been at risk of running off the end of the S-curve, and weâre just the latest to spend our twenties flirting with it.
And, as you said months ago, in a different context,
If weâre not aiming at enlightenment (i.e. the renunciation of the world is not in play) then perhaps emotion is good. The Good, even. Itâs hard to find a utilitarian who doesnât make use of it for a moral backbone these days. Absent god, itâs pretty hard to know where else to look.
Hereâs one space where that âa moral backboneâ â emotion â intersects with our attempts to re[s]train our own reflexive fire-starting tendencies:
§ 2. Law and Manners
Recently, The Econtalk Podcast turned its attention old essay by a man who was an archetype of Upper Class Britishness in name, title, and orientation: the Right Honourable Lord John Fletcher Moulton, Baron Moulton, GBE, KCB, PC, FRS, FRAS. In 1918 â or perhaps 1919; weâre not sure â Old Mate Moulton gave an after-dinner speech titled âLaw and Mannersâ. He opened his speech â forgive the length! â as follows:
In order to explain this extraordinary title I must ask you to follow me in examining the three great domains of Human Action. First comes the domain of Positive Law, where our actions are prescribed by laws binding upon us which must be obeyed. Next comes the domain of Free Choice, which includes all those actions as to which we claim and enjoy complete freedom. But between these two there is a third large and important domain in which there rules neither Positive Law nor Absolute Freedom. In that domain there is no law which inexorably determines our course of action, and yet we feel that we are not free to choose as we would. The degree of this sense of a lack of complete freedom in this domain varies in every case. It grades from a consciousness of a Duty nearly as strong as Positive Law, to a feeling that the matter is all but a question of personal choice. Some might wish to parcel out this domain into separate countries, calling one, for instance, the domain of Duty, another the domain of Public Spirit, another the domain of Good Form; but I prefer to look at it as all one domain, for it has one and the same characteristic throughout â it is the domain of Obedience to the Unenforceable. The obedience is the obedience of a man to that which he cannot be forced to obey. He is the enforcer of the law upon himself.
One of the reasons why I have chosen this as the subject on which to speak is that I have spent my life as a commissioner for delimiting the frontier line which divides this domain from the realm of Positive Law. I have had to decide so frequently whether Law could say, âYou must,â or regretfully to say, âI must leave it to you.â This is the land in which all those whom the Law cannot reach take refuge. It might be thought from such a description that I wished to annex that country and bring it under the rule of Positive Law. That is not the case. The infinite variety of circumstances surrounding the individual and rightly influencing his action make it impossible to subject him in all things to rules rigidly prescribed and duly enforced. Thus there was wisely left the intermediate domain which, so far as Positive Law is concerned, is a land of freedom of action, but in which the individual should feel that he was not wholly free. This country which lies between Law and Free Choice I always think of as the domain of Manners. To me, Manners in this broad sense signifies the doing that which you should do although you are not obliged to do it. I do not wish to call it Duty, for that is too narrow to describe it, nor would I call it Morals for the same reason. It might include both, but it extends beyond them. It covers all cases of right doing where there is no one to make you do it but yourself.
For Moulton â and for Russ Roberts & Michael Munger commenting on Moulton â we ought to attend to the so-called âdomain of mannersâ for the following reason: while we all have a set of reflexes, we can partly cultivate and re-form those impulses. Such âcultivationâ happens through effort, habit, and self-enforced obedience to (arbitrary) rules. We can, says Moulton (& Roberts & Munger), train ourselves to feel different emotions about different (potential) actions. This is true â says M(&R&M) â even though itâs implausible that weâll become more deliberatively-Good-Maximising in each individual moment. The thoughts and actions that we inscribe on our hearts â consciously at first â become, with time, habit, and then reflex. From Marcus Aurelius: âsuch as are thy habitual thoughts, such also will be the character of thy mind; for the soul is dyed by the thoughtsâ (Meditations 5.16).
For our purposes, letâs take a version of this as given. We watery, rubbery, mostly-monkey humans can â with effort â partly change our dispositions. Doing so is easier than âmagically becoming more deliberativeâ in every moment.
Moultonâs description of âobedience to the unenforceableâ is, I think, most naturally read as a call to live as if bound by laws that we set for ourselves. What Moulton is making is a seemingly paradoxical suggestion: we can end up making more & better âdecisions of meaningâ in our lives by accepting that most of the time, we donât really make decisions at all. We improve our collective impact by each, as individuals, spending most of our effort on making marginal alterations to what you call âthe rubbery contours of the selfâ. Constant conscious calculation is a doomed project; becoming a person whose reflexes tend more towards The Good is not.
The trouble, as I see it, is that Moultonâs account â in isolation â gives us basically no way to decide on what âmannersâ we ought to cultivate. If we are to bind ourselves to laws that we set for ourselves, how do we go about generating the unenforceable-but-obeyed? Whatâs the framework for evaluating a potential âmannerâ?
More importantly, if we take metaphors of cultivation as âha ha only seriousâ talk, evaluating potential âmannersâ must take account of an ecology of agents. Itâs not just a question of âshould I bind myself to this rule?â; itâs also a question of âshould I bind myself to this rule, given that Iâm a member of overlapping communities of agents, each â to greater and lesser degrees â also binding themselves to rules?â.
So. We look around. Itâs obvious. We take stupid risks. Weâre not okay. We donât trust each other, or ourselves. You hope
that as this generation ages weâll do what our parents and grandparents and all the rest did, and compromise just enough to stretch out the curve and pass it on.
Eventually (in ascending order of strangeness) I want to convince you that:
- There are coherent strategies for compromise;
- The not-totally-insane strategies are all necessary consequences of contemporary work on decision theory (especially functional decision theory, acausal normalcy, and some bargaining notions);
- The most coherent strategies are all, in some sense, âutilitarian in the seminar room; deontologist in the streetsâ accounts of practical ethics;
- Most such strategies suggest âmannersâ which do not look like current Majority Middle Class Culture; and,
- Most such strategies do closely resemble (and justify) something like an anarchist âpraxisâ â albeit one which most closely resonates with what Audrey Tang has called âconservative anarchismâ.
As youâll see, Iâm mostly interested in articulating all of this in terms of inter-temporal, intra-personal, and inter-cultural interactions. (And I think this also connects to some work on communication.)
(btw, as jargon: let your âcultureâ be, at least in part, the egregore which suggests your ambient âmannersâ; the things that â by upbringing and context, not deliberation â you feel you âoughtâ to do, even though âthere is no one to make you do it but yourselfâ.)
In what remains of this letter, as foundation for points 1-5 above, I want to sketch a case study in âmannersâ. More importantly, I want to tease out â from the case study â a recognition that there are spaces in which we (as a society) seem to demand deep commitment to non-utilitarian âmannersâ from some specific people, even when those manners would be harmful if universally adopted. And then, I want you to think about how we might go about justifying such âmannersâ on utilitarian grounds (via coördination).
§ 3. The Case Study: âProfessionalâ âEthicsâ
Thereâs a traditional view of âProfessional Ethicsâ, stylised as follows:
- When you enter into a profession, thereâs a set of standards that you have to uphold.
- The set of standards â the set of rules that you, when acting in your profession, are required to uphold â are different to the standards youâre required to uphold in other circumstances.
- The professional standards are more stringent than Normal Life in some respects.
- Some of the standards are legally enforced. Others are socially maintained.
- Not every professional standard is equally legible. Some are little more than vibe.
- All of this is good, and sensible, and justified.
Take the concrete archetype: a medical doctor. Doctors have a relatively well-defined set of professional ethics. There are legal standards that doctors have to uphold, but which non-doctors donât have to uphold. Thereâs a set of licensing standards, too; an overlapping legal magisterium in which the profession governs itself. Thereâs a set of legible-to-other-doctors (but not legally enshrined) norms. A set of more broadly-socially-legible norms also. And then thereâs an ancient oath. In most juristictions today, the Hippocratic Oath cuts across all of the above. You can be criminally liable for medical malpractice, sure, but you can also be symbolically liable; you can be shamed, be spiritually in the breach. And as anyone whoâs had experience with doctors knows, the effect of this is sometimes weird.
(This is not just true of doctors, but letâs focus on the doctor case for now.)
Last year, I got mild pericarditis from a covid vaccine. (It was worth it; the vax is great.) Because chest pain is stressful for everyone, I went to the emergency room three times. Twice, I was admitted. In both instances, once I was admitted, the standard for me leaving the hospital was in practice higher than the standard it was to admit me. You walk in, complain of chest pain. Quite quickly, everyone involved knows that the case is (a) moderate, (b) explained, and (c) absolutely fine. But now the doctor has seen you. Youâre their patient. You canât just leave, because they have a duty of care â legal, but also moral & professional-ethical â which theyâve internalised as having ânaturallyâ come into being in the moment of their interaction with you. Theyâre not just A Doctor, now, but Your Doctor; youâre not just a person, but A Patient.
While there is a kind of precautionary impulse in operation â no doctor wants to be reckless, or be seen to be reckless â the generating function for that impulse is what I want to focus on. Itâs not only that doctors are worried about being sued. Itâs that doctors are worried about being bad doctors. This latter concern is at least in part a consequence of a relational ethics that has been entangled with, embedded in, and constituted by an institution. Being a âBad Doctorâ doesnât ontologically reduce to âfailing to maximise welfareâ, or even âfailing to maximise the welfare of the patients in your careâ.
The two times I was admitted, there was shared-but-not-common knowledge that it was a combination of âoptimal resource allocation be damnedâ and âthe details of this case mean that we Really Must Do Xâ. In the ER, every doctor and nurse said the same two things, in two very different modes:
- âWeâve seen a tonne of these cases, from young men who look exactly like you, and itâs totally fineâ (this said casually, informally; like normal humans), and
- âBecause itâs one of these vaccine side effects, we do have to formally flag it in The System, and we Should Probably Not Let You Goâ (this said in a role-based deference to an invisible).
The time that I wasnât admitted, it felt like I was encouraging a conspiracy of reasonableness. Me, a doctor, and a nurse. Me explicitly saying âyou guys have better things to do, right?â and âyou seem so busy, I wouldnât want to waste your timeâ while gesturing to the quietest ER room Iâve ever seen. Me pushing further, as if merely curious: âso whatâs the process for a case getting added to the database?â. Them picking on my not-so-subtle hints that I would be super happy if they acted like less like Medical Professionals in that moment (and skipped the relational performances that they were in-theory obliged to enact).
Itâs well established, I think, that we donât want doctors to think âgloballyâ. In virtue fiction, such as The West Wing, we also want them to make the earnest case for their non-utilitarian thinking to their patronising & sexist interlocutors:
President Bartlet: Alright, Eisenmengerâs Syndrome.
First Lady: Itâs a cyanotic heart condition. Thereâs something called ventricular septal defect.
PB: The Ayatollahâs son has it.
FL: Am I dreaming, or are you talking to me about foreign policy? Youâre not worried the skyâs gonna fall down?
PB: No, but Iâm concerned about spousal abuse.
FL: Whatâs the problem Jed? Donât tell me thereâs a problem with State.
PB: The only doctor available wonât do it.
FL: Heâs Jewish?
PB: Persian.
FL: He doesnât have a choice.
PB: Abbey â
FL: He doesnât. Doctors arenât instruments of the State, and theyâre not allowed to choose patients on spec.
PB: I canât order him to do it.
FL: Yes you can.
PB: Through the power vested in me by you?
FL: Samuel Mudd set Boothâs leg after he shot Lincoln. Doctors are liable in this country [if] they donât treat the patient right in front of them.
PB: Just for the record, this is why we donât talk about foreign policy â which we do, and you donât think we do it enough â
FL: Why?
PB: Because Samuel Mudd was tried and convicted of treason for setting that leg.
FL: So?
PB: What âsoâ?!
FL: So thatâs the way it goes. You set the leg.
PB: âThe patient right in front of them.â
FL: Yes.
PB: Alright. Go back to the sewing thing.
FL: Itâs the Womanâs ⊠never mind.
Notice the slide. A concern over global effects (and a humanâs strongly-held convictions) transitions to a brief reminder of a professionâs special legal liability, and then almost immediately to reinforcement of a kind of relational, quasi-spiritual obligation.
Here in our virtue fiction, we donât want to hear the (reasonable) argument that a doctor tried for treason would lose all future opportunities to help other patients, or that one who saves the life of a war criminal might cause more deaths than they save. We want to hear deference to professional ethics and special relation.
If everyone acted the way that doctors are supposed to act in the way that First Lady Abbey Bartlet is suggesting above, I think itâs pretty obvious that society would be worse off. And yet we want some people to do more than merely act this way when âat workâ. We want them to naturalise a way of being this way in every moment of their lives. Just as a cop is never ânot a copâ (even when off-duty), and a priest doesnât breach the seal of the confessional the moment they leave the church, doctors have the ethics of their profession inscribed on their souls.
The question is: whatâs the coarse-grained steelman case for such a thing?