after countless exasperated pleas for a simpler and nicer world where people donât play games with each other, i realize i may have autistically failed to account for the fact that many people enjoy playing games â @hyperdiscogirl
Hereâs the thing about humans: most of the time, the things theyâre optimising for are not the things they will âon reflectionâ and when asked to verbalise claim that theyâre optimising for. Anyone who optimises coherently and legibly â even a little bit â reliably stands out, is strange, is scary. (See also the Empty World Hypothesis.)
that any non-utilitarian intervention into the field of moral duty will create (utilitarian) winners and losers, and that perversion of the established order will warp the people involved. Possibly for the better, of course, but under pressure, their metal will warp any which way unless itâs a tight mould. To actually improve things, the intervention has to follow its call to the good with stopgaps for the chill draft of perverse consequences, and then follow all that with some kind of sticky coating against the effect of time and moral slippage.
Itâs true that all kinds â subjects & objects; people & their norms â do strange things under pressure. But perhaps our terminology is getting in the way of our introspective access, here, to our detriment.
In my last, I promised to eventually convince you that
There are coherent strategies for compromise;
The not-totally-insane strategies are all necessary consequences of contemporary work on decision theory (especially functional decision theory, acausal normalcy, and some bargaining notions);
The most coherent strategies are all, in some sense, âutilitarian in the seminar room; deontologist in the streetsâ accounts of practical ethics;
Most such strategies suggest âmannersâ which do not look like current Majority Middle Class Culture; and,
Most such strategies do closely resemble (and justify) something like an anarchist âpraxisâ â albeit one which most closely resonates with what Audrey Tang has called âconservative anarchismâ.
Seen in outline form, I admit that this project is monstrous and unwieldy. Even in my head, it feels unmanageable. (The implied reading lists feel even moreso.) However, I think your points about the Hippocratic Oath give me a good way in. A bite-sized place to start.
As you say,
Itâs no wonder the original Hippocratic oath spends so much time stipulating the ways in which the maker is allowed to benefit from their knowledge â given how inconvenient it can be to the bearer, the wonder is that every doctor isnât a self-aggrandising, profit-seeking monster.
Frankly, youâre asking a fucking good question: why isnât self-aggrandising profit-seeking what we universally see? Why arenât doctors literally always âPharisaic fame-hunters and degenerate playersâ?
By way of answer, you point to a broader regime of social/cultural persuasion, in which âlose now, win laterâ or semi-secret âmetaphysical winnerâ is the name of the game. We motivate our Doctors to follow their special oaths to their own detriments by (credibly) promising advantage and boon. Specialisation and trade are entangled concepts, even and perhaps especially in the moral domain.
My answer, though, today, comes as a gesture towards one component of my first (outlined) point above. I claim that there exist âcoherent strategies for compromiseâ. While itâs true that the most common such mechanisms arenât the most coherent, they point in the direction of more & maximally coherent versions. We donât talk about them in these terms because the most widespread instances are so ânaturalâ that we rarely think of them as strategies or compromises at all. In their degenerate form, terms like âgetting byâ or âliving as an adultâ seem far more natural. Moreover, even when instantiated in deeply imperfect ways, such compromise strategies donât necessarily involve what I think youâd call âwarpâ. Theyâre still somewhat positive sum and mostly non-self-coercing. Not all tight moulds and sticky coatings.
As we all at this point hopefully know, modern psychology is mostly unimportant hogwash. The same goes for pretty much anything with âbehaviouralâ in its name. So letâs stick to a felt sense that weâve both (a) previously discussed, and (b) can easily introspect about: our selves âagainstâ our selves. This is the easiest place to identify ânatural compromiseâ strategies which are of the sort that explain our Doctors. [Iâll leave generalisation of such coordination & compromise âstrategiesâ to the level of interpersonal/cultural phenomena for another day.]
Seeing the results of a lil twitter poll thread, Sarah Constantin writes
Solid majorities say that theyâre usually not doing âwhat they think they shouldâ⌠and wouldnât opt to self-modify to always do what they think they should. Ethics & self-improvement enthusiasts, what would you say to such people?
Letâs assume that thereâs no âmonkey pawâ fear substantially interfering with these results. That is, letâs assume that most of the 50.9% of people who said ânoâ to this question â âIf you push the button, you are guaranteed to spend every second of the rest of your life doing exactly and only what you think you should be doing at that moment. Do you push the button?â â had in mind a hypothetical situation in which their actions were altered, rather than their desires or preferences or ought-generating mechanisms or whatever.
Whatâs going on here? The degree to which you are divided is the degree to which you are conquered. Are 50.9% of people saying that theyâre happy being conquered? Are they saying that theyâre happy â or, if not happy, somehow âsatisfiedâ â with a status quo in which they feel guilty for not doing what they themselves think that they ought to do?
No. I think whatâs going on, here, is actually pretty intuitive and paradoxically coherent:
When someone asks you whether youâre currently doing what you think you should be doing, theyâre asking you to play along with a linguistic & social game which is premised on the existence and operation of a singular, identifiable, legible âYouâ.
For a human, there is no such unified self. âYouâ is a lossy compression.
Most of language and social life works this way. We tell stories to ourselves and each other about our selves and each other, and these stories usually involve protagonist characters with legible goals and motivations.
Yet almost everyone telling those stories can also, privately, acknowledge that they are often surprised or disappointed my their own actions and motivations. They know that they can waver and be uncertain; that one feels âmixedâ feelings almost all of the time. And almost everyone feels some amount of conflict with (and distance from) their intertemporal âselfâ: shame at past actions, confusion as they examine past decisions, a sense of âgrowthâ and âchangeâ â of being alienated from oneâs past self â which is only sometimes positive.
Most people handle the conflict between ânarrative of coherent protagonistâ and âphenomenological access to incoherenceâ, on some level, by doing a mixture of two things:
- they flinch away from any kind of introspection which would reveal the incoherence too starkly; and,
- they make deals, trades, and promises within themselves until a coarse-grained/higher-level âcoherenceâ can be reestablished.
We all know the latter phenomenon. âIâll let myself watch TV once Iâve sent these emails,â for example, or âI wonât eat any more chocolate today, but Iâll let myself have some tomorrowâ. We give ourselves treats. We give ourselves punishments.
Most people (sometimes) defect on the promises they make to themselves, and feel bad about their defections. Most people have adopted some kind of a system for Mostly Getting By in the world despite the existence of conflicting desires, motivations, goals, and worldviews âwithin themselvesâ. For most people, that system is one with limits on intrapersonal violence.
In Sarah Constantinâs poll, 50.9% of people are signalling â with varying degrees of âselfâ-consciousness â that whatever system theyâve adopted for dealing with the lack of unification involves some amount of pre-commitment to not do things similar to pressing this hypothetical button. Itâs a kind of âselfâ-âacceptanceâ rule, for weird & mutually-assured-destruction senses of the words âacceptanceâ and âselfâ. Something like, no part of me will engage in an action which would completely destroy some other part of me, because that way lies annihilation. It would, perhaps, be ârationalâ to press the button in the hypothetical, because itâs a decisive move. A pivotal act. Most people, though, are not so good at decoupling from context and answering the hypothetical as stated. They signal, even in the hypothetical, their commitment to a personal, private pact.
In most cases, a tacit self-agreement of this form involves broader intrapersonal cooperations. One generates feelings of resistance in oneâs viscera. One erects half-conscious defences against practices which look (to your parliament of subagents) as if they might lead to bleaching all the corals of your inner world and calling it perfection.
In the modern world, most people â including myself â do a bad job of keeping their internal ârule of law but not by menâ cooperation system going in a reliable way. A lot of the time, the concept of personal integrity is entangled with promises & debts; external forces do substantial and often deliberate damage to our ability to keep promises to ourselves. And so (at least in self-report) most end up deferring to those external forces: âpeople report feeling most authentic when they are doing what external society values, not when they are acting in accord with their actual personalitiesâ (Baumeister 56). Yet none of this should be taken as evidence that the system is fully absent, or could not be better if circumstances were different or details were re-engineered.
If things can be worse, they can also be better. The direction towards self-consistency and self-cooperation is one in which
- âYouâ can make non-coercive, positive-sum deals âwith yourselfâ; and,
- âYouâ can trust yourself to keep the bargain made.
And so the idealised Doctor is one who, in taking an oath, has verbalised and socialised an always-already internal compact. A compact from which âtheyâ would have no desire to defect. Theyâve made a deal with themselves, in that place deep within their soul where their subagents argue, debate, listen to one another, and eventually agree that itâs in everyoneâs collective interest to do X. In such a case, the âmotivationâ to follow special moral rules isnât entangled with self-destruction, or self-abnegation. It is, instead, a natural consequence. Stopping for the drunk young man slumped in the archway is merely a positive externality.
As flies to wanton boys are we to the gods. They kill us for the sport. Soon the science will not only be able to slow down the ageing of the cells, soon the science will fix the to the state. And so, we become eternal. Only accidents, crimes, wars will still kill us. But unfortunately crimes and wars will multiply. I love football.